Samson Corwell

Recommended Posts

I'm the sort of person who approaches politics from a legal perspective. The Constitution is a swell document and the Bill of Rights is an icon of America. Most people are surprised to learn that the Bill of Rights originally applied only to the federal government.

Now, I usually get into tussles with some conservatives over the role of the Supreme Court. My largest problem that I have with these particular ones is over the incorporation doctrine. When the subject comes up I often get bizarre remarks about it being a usurpation of "the people" (hello, Jean-Jacques Rousseau), the separation of church and state being a curb on religious freedom, that I'm saying that "the people" don't retain any rights, or a bunch of unrelated crap. I was even called a statist once for agreeing with it (snarl word, ahoy). One of the people opposed to it was someone who supported slave labor for illegal immigrants (I then made a snarky reference to North Korea), so I think you can get a sense of what these people have seemed like to me. (They covet the Tenth Amendment, but the Ninth Amendment? **** it.)

Can I get any of your opinions on it?

Link to comment
Share on other sites

For all the brilliance and insights of the framers, they failed to recognize the potential for government to expand its boundaries and weaken restrictions on its power over time. I don't blame them for their failing; there is no way in 1790 they could have foreseen the growth of a massive fourth branch of government - the unelected and unaccountable administrative state. They also could not have appreciated the potential for state governments to expand in size and authority and become tyrannies in themselves. In the founding era, the only recognizable threat was concentrated federal power. I'm a proponent of decentralized knowledge and consumer choice, so the idea of states as laboratories is appealing to me. However, we don't want the mad scientists in our more progressive states getting too crazy experimenting on our citizenry, so it's necessary to establish some floor of inalienable rights that cannot be violated by any state. My regret is the Bill of Rights, and the Constitution generally, isn't stronger and more explicit on what government may not do (or become for that matter). We've seen how something as seemingly straightforward as the Commerce Clause can be warped beyond all recognition through incrementalist encroachment until it becomes a de facto general policing power for the U.S. Congress.

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Very inteesting thread.

I have learned the hard way from Mark Levin to read the notes in decisions, the State Conventions, etc.

These are revealing:

CRS Annotated Constitution Ninth Amendment -- Table of Contents

The enumeration in the Constitution, of certain rights, shall not be construed to deny or disparage others retained by the people.

Aside from contending that a bill of rights was unnecessary, the Federalists responded to those opposing ratification of the Constitution because of the lack of a declaration of fundamental rights by arguing that inasmuch as it would be impossible to list all rights it would be dangerous to list some because there would be those who would seize on the absence of the omitted rights to assert that government was unrestrained as to those.1 Madison adverted to this argument in presenting his proposed amendments to the House of Representatives. “It has been objected also against a bill of rights, that, by enumerating particular exceptions to the grant of power, it would disparage those rights which were not placed in that enumeration; and it might follow by implication, that those rights which were not singled out, were intended to be assigned into the hands of the General Government, and were consequently insecure. This is one of the most plausible arguments I have ever heard against the admission of a bill of rights into this system; but, I conceive, that it may be guarded against. I have attempted it, as gentlemen may see by turning to the last clause of the fourth resolution.”2 It is clear from its text and from Madison’s statement that the Amendment states but a rule of construction, making clear that a Bill of Rights might not by implication be taken to increase the powers of the national government in areas[p.1504]not enumerated, and that it does not contain within itself any guarantee of a right or a proscription of an infringement.3 Recently, however, the Amendment has been construed to be positive affirmation of the existence of rights which are not enumerated but which are nonetheless protected by other provisions.

The Ninth Amendment had been mentioned infrequently in decisions of the Supreme Court4 until it became the subject of some exegesis by several of the Justices in Griswold v. Connecticut.5 There a statute prohibiting use of contraceptives was voided as an infringement of the right of marital privacy. Justice Douglas, writing the opinion of the Court, asserted that the “specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have penumbras, formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life and substance.”6 Thus, while privacy is nowhere mentioned, it is one of the values served and protected by the First Amendment, through its protection of associational rights, and by the Third, the Fourth, and the Fifth Amendments as well. The Justice recurred to the text of the Ninth Amendment, apparently to support the thought that these penumbral rights are protected by one Amendment or a complex of Amendments despite the absence of a specific reference. Justice Goldberg, concurring, devoted several pages to the Amendment.

“The language and history of the Ninth Amendment reveal that the Framers of the Constitution believed that there are additional fundamental rights, protected from governmental infringement, which exist alongside those fundamental rights specifically mentioned in the first eight constitutional amendments. . . . To hold that a right so basic and fundamental and so deep–rooted in our society as the right of privacy in marriage may be infringed because that right is not guaranteed in so many words by the first eight amendments to the Constitution is to ignore the Ninth[p.1505]Amendment and to give it no effect whatsoever. Moreover, a judicial construction that this fundamental right is not protected by the Constitution because it is not mentioned in explicit terms by one of the first eight amendments or elsewhere in the Constitution would violate the Ninth Amendment. . . . Nor do I mean to state that the Ninth Amendment constitutes an independent source of right protected from infringement by either the States or the Federal Government. Rather, the Ninth Amendment shows a belief of the Constitution’s authors that fundamental rights exist that are not expressly enumerated in the first eight amendments and an intent that the list of rights included there not be deemed exhaustive.”7 While, therefore, neither opinion sought to make of the Ninth Amendment a substantive source of constitutional guarantees, both did read it as indicating a function of the courts to interpose a veto with regard to legislative and executive efforts to abridge other fundamental rights. In this case, both opinions seemed to concur that the fundamental right claimed and upheld was derivative of several express rights and in this case, really, the Ninth Amendment added almost nothing to the argument. But if there is a claim of a fundamental right which cannot reasonably be derived from one of the provisions of the Bill of Rights, even with the Ninth Amendment, how is the Court to determine, first, that it is fundamental, and second, that it is protected from abridgment?8

Footnotes
1 The Federalist No. 84 (Modern Library ed. 1937).
2 1 Annals of Congress 439 (1789). Earlier, Madison had written to Jefferson: “My own opinion has always been in favor of a bill of rights; provided it be so framed as not to imply powers not meant to be included in the enumeration. . . . I have not viewed it in an important light—1. because I conceive that in a certain degree . . . the rights in question are reserved by the manner in which the federal powers are granted. 2. because there is great reason to fear that a positive declaration of some of the most essential rights could not be obtained in the requisite latitude. I am sure that the rights of conscience in particular, if submitted to public definition would be narrowed much more than they are likely ever to be by an assumed power.” 5 Writings of James Madison, 271–72 (G. Hunt ed. 1904). See also 3 J. Story, Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States 1898 (1833).
3 To some extent, the Ninth and Tenth Amendments overlap with respect to the question of unenumerated powers, one of the two concerns expressed by Madison, more clearly in his letter to Jefferson but also present in his introductory speech. Supra, n.2 and accompanying text.
4 In United Public Workers v. Mitchell, 330 U.S. 75, 94–95 (1947) , upholding the Hatch Act, the Court said: “We accept appellant’s contention that the nature of political rights reserved to the people by the Ninth and Tenth Amendments [is] involved. The right claimed as inviolate may be stated as the right of a citizen to act as a party official or worker to further his own political views. Thus we have a measure of interference by the Hatch Act and the Rules with what otherwise would be the freedom of the civil servant under the First, Ninth, and Tenth Amendments.” See Ashwander v. TVA, 297 U.S. 288, 300– 11 (1936), and Tennessee Electric Power Co. v. TVA, 306 U.S. 118, 143–44 (1939) . See also Justice Chase’s opinion in Calder v. Bull, 3 U.S. (3 Dall.) 386, 388 (1798), and Justice Miller for the Court in Loan Ass’n v. Topeka, 87 U.S. (20 Wall.) 655, 662–63 (1875).
5 381 U.S. 479 (1965). [this is the Griswold case with penumbras emanations and other magical inventions by Justice Douglas]
6 Id. at 484. The opinion was joined by Chief Justice Warren and by Justices Clark, Goldberg, and Brennan.
7 Id. at 488, 491, 492. Chief Justice Warren and Justice Brennan joined this opinion. Justices Harlan and White concurred id. at 499, 502, without alluding to the Ninth Amendment, but instead basing their conclusions on substantive due process, finding that the state statute “violates basic values implicit in the concept of ordered liberty,” (citing Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 325 (1937) ). Id. at 500. It would appear that the source of the fundamental rights to which Justices Douglas and Goldberg referred must be found in a concept of substantive due process, despite the former’s express rejection of this ground. Id. at 481–82. Justices Black and Stewart dissented. Justice Black viewed the Ninth Amendment ground as essentially a variation of the due process argument under which Justices claimed the right to void legislation as irrational, unreasonable, or offensive, without finding any violation of an express constitutional provision.
8 Notice the recurrence to the Ninth Amendment as a “constitutional ‘saving clause”’ in Chief Justice Burger’s plurality opinion in Richmond Newspapers v. Virginia, 448 U.S. 555, 579–80 & n.15 (1980). Scholarly efforts to establish the clause as a substantive protection of rights include J. Ely, Democracy and Distrust—A Theory of Judicial Review (Cambridge: 1980), 34–41; and C. Black, Decision According to Law (New York: 1981), critically reviewed in W. Van Alstyne, Slouching Toward Bethlehem with the Ninth Amendment, 91 L. J. 207 (1981). For a collection of articles on the Ninth Amendment, see The Rights Retained by the People: The History and Meaning of the Ninth Amendment (Randy E. Barnett, ed., 1989).

Roe v. Wade is another.

It's non-specificity has been a place where even "strict constructionists" shrink from...

That is mentioned prominantly in this link...as well as the eight (8) footnotes above...

http://www.law.cornell.edu/anncon/html/amdt9_user.html#fnb1

The Ninth Amendment had been mentioned infrequently in decisions of the Supreme Court4 until it became the subject of some exegesis by several of the Justices in Griswold v. Connecticut.5 There a statute prohibiting use of contraceptives was voided as an infringement of the right of marital privacy. Justice Douglas, writing the opinion of the Court, asserted that the “specific guarantees in the Bill of Rights have penumbras, formed by emanations from those guarantees that help give them life and substance.”6

A...

Link to comment
Share on other sites

Create an account or sign in to comment

You need to be a member in order to leave a comment

Create an account

Sign up for a new account in our community. It's easy!

Register a new account

Sign in

Already have an account? Sign in here.

Sign In Now